All Episodes
Dec. 3, 2021 - Lex Fridman Podcast
02:15:42
Peter Woit: Theories of Everything & Why String Theory is Not Even Wrong | Lex Fridman Podcast #246
| Copy link to current segment

Time Text
The following is a conversation with Peter White, a theoretical physicist at Columbia, outspoken critic of string theory, and the author of the popular physics and mathematics blog called Not Even Wrong.
This is the Lex Friedman Podcast.
To support it, please check out our sponsors in the description.
And now, here's my conversation with Peter White.
You're both a physicist and a mathematician.
So let me ask, what is the difference between physics and mathematics?
Well, there's kind of a conventional understanding of the subject that they're two quite different things, so that mathematics is about making The more interesting thing is that there's a wide variety of what people do as mathematics, what they do as physics, and there's a significant overlap.
That, I think, is actually the Much, much, very, very interesting area.
And if you go back kind of far enough in history and look at figures like Newton or something, I mean, at that point, you can't really tell, you know, was Newton a physicist or a mathematician?
The mathematicians will tell you he's a mathematician, the physicist will tell you he's a physicist.
But he would say he's a philosopher.
Yeah, that's interesting.
But, yeah, anyway, there was kind of no such distinction then.
It's more of a modern thing and...
But anyway, I think these days there's a very interesting space in between the two.
So in the story of the 20th century and the early 21st century, what is the overlap between mathematics and physics, would you say?
Well, I think it's actually become very, very complicated.
I think it's really interesting to see a lot of what my colleagues in the math department are doing.
Most of what they're doing, they're doing all sorts of different things, but most of them have some kind of overlap with physics or other.
So, I mean, I'm personally interested in one particular aspect of this overlap, which I think has a lot to do with the most fundamental ideas about physics and about mathematics.
But There's just, you kind of see this really everywhere at this point.
Which particular overlap are you looking at, group theory?
Yeah, so at least the way it seems to me that if you look at physics and look at our most successful laws of fundamental physics, they have a certain kind of mathematical structure.
It's based upon certain kind of mathematical objects and geometry, connections and curvature, the spinners, the Dirac equation.
And this very deep mathematics provides kind of a unifying set of ways of thinking that allow you to make a unified theory of physics.
But the interesting thing is that if you go to mathematics and look at what's been going on in mathematics the last 50, 100 years, and even especially recently, there's a...
Similarly, some kind of unifying ideas which bring together different areas of mathematics and which have been especially powerful in number theory recently.
And there's a book, for instance, by Edward Frankel about love and math.
Yeah, that book's great.
I recommend it highly. It's partially accessible, but it is a nice audio book that I listened to while running an exceptionally long distance, like across the San Francisco Bridge.
And there's something magic about the way he writes about it.
But some of the group theory in there is a little bit difficult.
Yeah. It's a problem with any of these things.
To kind of really say what's going on and make it accessible is very hard.
He, in this book and elsewhere, I think, takes the attitude that kinds of mathematics he's interested in and that he's talking about provide kind of a grand unified theory of mathematics.
They bring together geometry and number theory and representation theory, a lot of different ideas in a really unexpected way.
But I think, to me, the most fascinating thing is if you look at the kind of grand unified theory of mathematics he's talking about, and you look at the physicists' kind of ideas about unification, it's more or less the same mathematical objects are appearing in both.
So it's this, I think there's a really, we're seeing a really strong indication that, you know, the deepest ideas that we're discovering about physics and some of the deepest ideas that mathematicians are learning about are really, are, you know, intimately connected.
Is there something, like, if I was five years old and you were trying to explain this to me, Is there ways to try to sneak up to what this unified world of mathematics looks like?
You said number theory, you said geometry, words like topology.
What does this universe begin to look like?
What should we imagine in our mind?
Is it a three-dimensional surface and we're trying to say something about it?
Is it triangles and squares and cubes?
What are we supposed to imagine in our minds?
Is this natural number?
What's a good thing to try for people that don't know any of these tools except maybe some basic calculus and geometry from high school that they should keep in their minds?
As to the unified world of mathematics that also allows us to explore the unified world of physics.
I mean, what I find kind of remarkable about this is the way in which we've discovered these ideas, but they're actually quite alien to our everyday understanding.
You know, we grow up in this three-spatial dimensional world, and we have intimate understanding of certain kinds of geometry and certain kinds of things, but...
that we've discovered in both math and physics are that they're not at all close, have any
obvious connection to kind of human everyday experience.
They're really quite different.
And I can say some of my initial fascination with this when I was
young and starting to learn about it was actually exactly this kind of arcane nature of these things.
It was a little bit like being told, well, there are these kind of semi-mystical experience that you can acquire by a long study and whatever, except that it was actually true.
There's actually evidence that this actually works.
So I'm a little bit wary of trying to give people that kind of thing, because I think it's mostly misleading.
But one thing to say is that geometry is a large part of it, and Maybe one interesting thing that's about some of the most recent ideas is that when we think about the geometry of our space and time, it's kind of three-spatial in one time dimension.
Physics is, in some sense, about something that's kind of four-dimensional, in a way.
And a really interesting thing about some of the recent developments in number theory have been to realize that These ideas that we were looking at, you know, naturally fit into a context where your theory is kind of four-dimensional.
So geometry is a big part of this, and we know a lot and feel a lot about, you know, two-, one-, two-, three-dimensional geometry.
So wait a minute. So we can at least rely on the four dimensions of space and time and say that we can get pretty far by working in those four dimensions?
I thought you were going to scare me that we're going to have to go to many, many, many, many more dimensions than that.
My point of view, which goes against a lot of these ideas about unification, is that, no, this is really...
Everything we know about really is about four dimensions, that...
And that you can actually understand a lot of these structures that we've been seeing in fundamental physics and in number theory just in terms of four dimensions.
It's in some sense I would claim has been kind of a mistake that physicists have made for decades and decades to try to go to higher dimensions, to try to formulate a theory in higher dimensions.
And then you're stuck with The problem is how do you get rid of all these extra dimensions that you've created?
Because we only ever see anything in four dimensions.
That kind of thing leads us astray, you think?
So creating all these extra dimensions just to give yourself extra degrees of freedom.
I mean, isn't that the process of mathematics?
It's to create all of these trajectories for yourself, but eventually you have to end up at a final place.
But it's okay to... It's okay to sort of create abstract objects on your path to proving something.
Yeah, certainly. And from a mathematician's point of view, mathematicians are also very different than physicists in that we like to develop very general theories.
If we have an idea, we want to see what's the greatest generality in which you can talk about it.
So from the point of view of most of the ways geometry is formulated by mathematicians, it really doesn't matter.
It works in any dimension.
We can do one, two, three, four, any number.
There's no particular... For most of geometry, there's no particular special thing but four.
Anyway, what physicists have been trying to do over the years is try to understand these fundamental theories in a geometrical way, and it's very tempting to kind of just start bringing in extra dimensions and using them to explain the structure, but typically this attempt kind of founders because you just don't know, you end up not being able to explain why we only see four.
It is nice in the space of physics that, like if you look at Fermat's last theorem, it's much easier to prove that there's no solution for n equals 3 than it is for the general case.
And so I guess that's the nice benefit of being a physicist, is you don't have to worry about the general case because we live in a universe with n equals 4 in this case.
Yeah, physicists are very interested in saying something about specific examples.
I find that interesting when I'm trying to do things in mathematics and I'm even teaching courses to mathematics students.
I find that I'm teaching them in a different way than most mathematicians because I'm very often very focused on examples, on what's kind of the crucial example that shows how this This powerful new mathematical technique, how it works and why you would want to do it.
And I'm less interested in kind of, you know, proving a precise theorem about exactly when it's going to work and when it's not going to work.
Do you usually think about really simple examples, like both for teaching and when you try to solve a difficult problem?
Do you construct like the simplest possible examples that captures the fundamentals of the problem and try to solve it?
Yeah, yeah, exactly.
That's often a really fruitful way to, if you've got some idea, just to kind of try to boil it down to what's the simplest situation in which this kind of thing is going to happen, and then try to really understand that.
And that is almost always a really good way to get insight into it.
Do you work with paper and pen?
Or like, for example, for me, coming from the programming side, if I look at a model, if I look at some kind of mathematical object, I like to mess around with it sort of numerically.
I just visualize different parts of it.
Visualize however I can.
So most of the work is like with neural networks, for example.
As you try to play with the simplest possible example and just to build up intuition by, you know, any kind of object has a bunch of variables in it.
And you start to mess around with them in different ways and visualize in different ways to start to build intuition.
Or do you go the Einstein route and just imagine Like, everything inside your mind and sort of build, like, thought experiments and then work purely on paper and pen.
Well, the problem with this kind of stuff that I'm interested in is you rarely can kind of...
It's rarely something that is really kind of...
Or even the simplest example, you can kind of see what's going on by looking at something happening in three dimensions.
Generally, the structures involved are...
Either they're more abstract, or if you try to kind of embed them in some kind of space where you could manipulate them in some kind of geometrical way, it's going to be a much higher dimensional space.
So even simple examples, embedding them into three-dimensional space, you're losing a lot.
Yeah, but to capture what you're trying to understand about them, you have to go to four or more dimensions, so it starts to get to be hard.
I mean, you can train yourself to try it as much as to kind of Think about things in your mind.
And, you know, I often use pad and paper, and I'm often, in my office, I often use the blackboard.
And you are kind of drawing things, but they're really kind of more abstract representations of how things are supposed to fit together.
And they're not really, unfortunately, not just kind of really living in three dimensions where you can understand.
Are we supposed to be sad or excited by the fact that our human minds can't fully comprehend the kind of mathematics you're talking about?
I mean, what do we make of that?
I mean, to me, that makes me quite sad.
It makes it seem like there's a giant mystery out there that we'll never truly get to experience directly.
It is kind of sad how difficult this is.
I mean, or I would put it a different way that...
You know, most questions that people have about this kind of thing, you can give them a true answer and really understand it, but the problem is one more of time.
It's like, yes, I could explain to you how this works, but you'd have to be willing to sit down with me and work at this repeatedly for...
For hours and days and weeks.
It's just going to take that long for your mind to really wrap itself around what's going on.
So that does make things inaccessible, which is sad.
But it's just kind of part of life that we all have a limited amount of time and we have to decide what we're going to do.
What we're going to spend our time doing.
Speaking of a limited amount of time, we only have a few hours, maybe a few days together here on this podcast.
Let me ask you the question of amongst many of the ideas that you work on in mathematics and physics, what is the most beautiful idea or one of the most beautiful ideas, maybe a surprising idea?
And once again, unfortunately, the way life works, we only have a limited time together to try to convey such an idea.
Okay. Well, actually, let me just tell you something.
I'm tempted to kind of start trying to explain what I think is this most powerful idea that brings together math and physics, ideas about groups and representations and how it fits in quantum mechanics.
But in some sense, I wrote a whole textbook about that, and I don't think we really have time to get very far into it.
Yeah. Well, can I actually, on a small tangent, you did write a paper towards the Grant Unified Theory of Mathematics and Physics.
Maybe you could step there first.
What is the key idea in that paper?
Well, I think we've kind of gone over that.
I think that the key idea is what we were talking about earlier, that...
Just kind of a claim that if you look and see what have been successful ideas in unification in physics over the last 50 years or so, and what's been happening in mathematics and the kind of thing that Frankel's book is about, that these are very much the same kind of mathematics.
And so it's kind of an argument that there really is...
You shouldn't be looking to unify just...
Math or just fundamental physics, but taking inspiration for looking for new ideas in fundamental physics, that they are going to be in the same direction of getting deeper into mathematics and looking for more inspiration in mathematics from these successful ideas about fundamental physics.
Could you put words to sort of the disciplines we're trying to unify?
So you said number theory.
Are we literally talking about all the major fields of mathematics?
So it's like the number theory, geometry, So the differential geometry, topology.
Yeah. So the, I mean, one name for this, that this is acquired in mathematics is the so-called Langlands program.
And so this started out in mathematics.
It's that, you know, Robert Langlands kind of realized that a lot of what people were doing in, that was starting to be really successful in number theory in the 60s.
And so that this actually was, Anyway, that this could be thought of in terms of these ideas about symmetry in groups and representations, and in a way that was also close to some ideas about geometry.
And then more later on in the 80s and 90s, there was something called geometric Langlands, that people realized that you could take what people have been doing in number theory in Langlands and just forget about the number theory and ask, what is this telling you about geometry?
And you get a whole, some new insights into certain kinds of geometry that way.
So it's, anyway, that's kind of the name for this area is Langlands and geometric Langlands.
And just recently in the last few months, there's been, there's kind of a really major paper that appeared by Peter Schulze and Laurent Farg, where they, you know, made, you know, a serious advance in trying to understand a very much Kind of a local problem of what happens in number theory near a certain prime number.
And they turned this into a problem of exactly the kind of geometric Langlands people had been doing, this kind of pure geometry problem.
And they found, by generalizing mathematics, they could actually reformulate it in that way, and it worked perfectly well.
One of the things that makes me sad is, you know, I'm a pretty knowledgeable person in the, what is it, at least I'm in the neighborhood of, like, theoretical computer science, right?
And it's still way out of my reach.
And so many people talk about, like, Langlands, for example, is one of the most brilliant people in mathematics and just really admires work.
And I can't, it's like almost I can't hear the music that he composed.
And it makes me sad.
Yeah. Well, I mean, I think, unfortunately, it's not just you.
I think even most mathematicians have no—really don't actually understand what this is about.
I mean, the group of people who really understand all these ideas—and so, for instance, this paper of Schultz and Farg that I was talking about, the number of people who really actually understand how that works is—anyway, move on.
Very, very small. I think even you'll find if you talk to mathematicians and physicists, even they will often feel that there's this really interesting sounding stuff going on, which I should be able to understand.
It's kind of in my own field I have a PhD in, but it still seems pretty clearly far beyond me right now.
Well, if we can step back to the question of beauty, is there an idea that maybe is a little bit smaller that you find beautiful in the space of mathematics or physics?
There's an idea that, you know, I kind of got a physics PhD and spent a lot of time learning about mathematics, and I guess it was embarrassing that I hadn't really actually understood this very simple idea until I kind of learned it when I actually started teaching math classes, which is that Maybe there's a simple way to explain the fundamental way in which algebra and geometry are connected.
So you normally think of geometry as about these spaces and these points, and you think of algebra as this very abstract thing about these abstract objects that satisfy certain kinds of relations.
You can multiply them and add them and do stuff, but it's completely abstract.
There's nothing geometric about it.
The kind of really fundamental idea that unifies algebra and geometry is to think whenever anybody gives you what you call an algebra, some abstract thing of things that you can multiply and add, that you should ask yourself, is that algebra the space of functions on some geometry?
So one of the most surprising examples of this, for instance, is a standard kind of thing that seems to have nothing to do with geometry is the integers.
You can multiply them and add them.
It's an algebra, but it seems to have nothing to do with geometry.
But if you ask yourself this question and ask, if somebody gives you an integer, can you think of it as a function on some space, on some geometry?
And it turns out that yes, you can, and the space is the space of prime numbers.
And so what you do is you just, if somebody gives you an integer, you can make a function on the prime numbers by just, you know, at each prime number, taking that integer modulo, that prime.
So if, as you say, I don't know, if you get given 10, you know, 10, and you ask what is its value at 2, well, it's It's 5 times 2, so mod 2, it's 0, so it has 0 at 1.
What is its value at 3?
Well, it's 9 plus 1, so it's 1 mod 3.
So it's 0 at 2, it's 1 at 3, and you can kind of keep going.
And so... This is really kind of a truly fundamental idea.
It's at the basis of what's called algebraic geometry, and it just links these two parts of mathematics that look completely different.
And it's just an incredibly powerful idea, and so much of mathematics emerges from this kind of simple relation.
So, you're talking about mapping from one discrete space to another.
For a second I thought perhaps mapping like a continuous space to a discrete space, like functions over a continuous space.
Well, yeah. Well, I mean, you can take...
If somebody gives you a space, you can ask...
You can say, well, let's...
And this is also... This is part of the same idea.
the part of the same idea is that if you try and do geometry
and somebody tells you here's a space, that what you should do is you should wait,
so say, wait a minute, maybe I should be trying to solve this using algebra.
And so if I do that, the way to start is, you give me the space,
I start to think about the functions on the space.
Okay, so for each point in the space, I associate a number.
I can take different kinds of functions and different kinds of values,
but basically functions on a space.
So what this insight is telling you is that if you're a geometer, often the way to work
is to change your problem into algebra by changing your space.
Stop thinking about your space and the points in it and think about the functions on it.
Got it. And if you're an algebraist and you've got these abstract algebraic gadgets that you're multiplying and adding, say...
Wait a minute, are those gadgets, can I think of them in some way as a function on a space?
What would that space be and what kind of functions would they be?
And that, going back and forth, really brings these two completely different looking areas of mathematics together.
Do you have particular examples where it allowed to prove some difficult things by jumping from one to the other?
Is that something that's a part of modern mathematics where such jumps are made?
Oh yeah, this is kind of all the time.
Much of modern number theory is kind of based on this idea.
And when you start doing this, you start to realize that you need simple things on one side, the algebra, start to require you to think about The other side about geometry in a new way, you have to kind of get a more sophisticated idea about geometry.
Or if you start thinking about the functions on a space, you may need a more sophisticated kind of algebra.
But in some sense, much or most of modern number theory is based upon this move to geometry.
And there's also a lot of geometry and topology is also based upon Yeah, change.
If you want to understand the topology of something, you look at the functions, you do Durham cohomology, and you get the topology.
Anyway. Well, let me ask you then the ridiculous question.
You said that this idea is beautiful.
Can you formalize the definition of the word beautiful, and why is this beautiful?
First, why is this beautiful, and second, what is beautiful?
And I think there are many different things you can find beautiful for different reasons.
I mean, I think in this context, the notion of beauty, I think, really is just kind of an idea is beautiful if it packages a huge amount of kind of power and information into something very simple.
So in some sense, I mean, you can almost kind of try and measure it in the sense of, you know, what are the implications of this idea?
What What non-trivial things does it tell you versus how simply can you express the idea?
So the level of compression correlates with beauty?
Yeah, that's one aspect of it.
And so you can start to tell that an idea is becoming uglier and uglier as you start kind of having to, you know, it doesn't quite do what you want, so you throw in something else to the idea and you keep doing that until you get what you want.
But that's how you know you're doing something uglier and uglier when you have to kind of keep adding in Getting more into what was originally a fairly simple idea and making it more and more complicated to get what you want.
Okay, so let's put some philosophical words on the table and try to make some sense of them.
One word is beauty.
Another one is simplicity, as you mentioned.
Another one is truth.
So, do you have a sense, if I give you two theories, one is Simpler, one is more complicated.
Do you have a sense of which one is more likely to be true to capture deeply the fabric of reality?
The simple one or the more complicated one?
Yeah, I think all of our evidence, what we see in the history of the subject is the simpler one.
Often it's a surprise, it's simpler in a surprising way, but Yeah, the kind of best theories we've been coming up with are ultimately, when not properly understood, relatively simple and much, much simpler than you would expect them to be.
Do you have a good explanation why that is?
Is it just because humans want it to be that way?
Are we just like ultra-biased and we just kind of convince ourselves that simple is better because we find simplicity beautiful?
Or is there something about our actual universe that at the core is simple?
My own belief is that there is something about a universe that's simple.
And I was trying to say that there is some kind of fundamental thing about math, physics, and physics and all this picture, which is...
Which is in some sense simple.
It's true that, you know, it's of course true that our minds are very limited and can certainly do certain things and not others.
So it's in principle possible that there's some great insight.
There are a lot of insights into the way the world works which just aren't accessible to us because that's not the way our minds work.
We don't. And that what we're seeing, this kind of simplicity, is just because that's all we ever have any hope of seeing.
So there's a brilliant physicist by the name of Sabine Hassenfelder who both agrees and disagrees with you, or I suppose agrees, that the final answer will be simple.
Yeah. But simplicity and beauty leads us astray in the local pockets of scientific progress.
Do you agree with her disagreement?
Do you disagree with her agreement?
And agree with the agreement and so on.
Yes, I found it was really fascinating reading your book.
And anyway, I was finding disagreeing with a lot, but then at the end when she says yes, when we find, when we actually figure this out, it will be simple.
Okay, so we agree in the end.
But does beauty lead us astray, which is the core thesis of her work in that book.
Actually, I guess I do disagree with her on that so much, I don't think.
And especially, and I actually fairly strongly disagree with her about sometimes the way she'll refer to math.
And so the problem is, you know, physicists and people in general just refer to it as math, and they're often meaning not what I would call math, which is the interesting ideas of math, but just some complicated calculation.
And so... I guess my feeling about it is more that it's very...
The problem with talking about simplicity and using simplicity as a guide is that it's very...
It's very easy to fool yourself, and it's very easy to decide to fall in love with an idea.
You have an idea, and you think, oh, this is great, and you fall in love with it.
Like any kind of love affair, it's very easy to believe that the object of your affections is much more beautiful than others might think, and that they really are.
That's very, very easy to do.
If you say, I'm just going to pursue ideas about Beauty and mathematics and this, it's extremely easy to just fool yourself, I think.
And I think that's a lot of what the story she was thinking of about where people have gone astray.
I would argue that it's more people.
It's not that there was some simple, powerful, wonderful idea which they'd found and it turned out not to be.
Not to be useful, but it was more that they kind of fooled themselves that this was actually a better idea than it really was, and that it was simpler and more beautiful than it really was, is a lot of the story.
I see, so it's not that the simplicity of beauty leads us astray, it's just people are people and they fall in love with whatever idea they have, and then they leave narratives around that idea, or they present it in such a way that emphasizes The simplicity and the beauty.
Yeah, that's part of it.
But, I mean, the thing about physics that you have is that you, you know, what really can tell...
If you can do an experiment and check and see if nature is really doing what your idea expects, then you do, in principle, have a way of really testing it.
And it's certainly true that if you...
You know, if you thought you had a simple idea and that doesn't work and you got into an experiment and what actually does work is maybe some more complicated version of it, that can certainly happen and that can be true.
I think her emphasis is more that I don't really disagree with is that Um, people should be concentrating on, um, when they're trying to develop better theories on more on, on self-consistency, not so much on beauty, but, you know, not, is this idea beautiful, but, you know, is there something about the theory which is not quite consistent and that, and use that as a guide to, that there's something wrong there, which needs fixing.
And, and so I think that part of her argument, I think I was, we're on the same page about it.
What is consistency and inconsistency?
What exactly?
Do you have examples in mind?
Well, it can be just simple inconsistency between theory and experiment.
So we have this great fundamental theory, but there are some things we see out there which don't seem to fit in it, like dark energy and dark matter, for instance.
But if there's something which you can't test experimentally, I think she would argue, and I would agree, that, for instance, if you're trying to think about gravity and how are you going to have a quantum theory of gravity, you should kind of Can you test any of your ideas with kind of a thought experiment?
Does this actually give a consistent picture of what's going to happen, of what happens in this particular situation or not?
So this is a good example.
You've written about this. Since quantum gravitational effects are really small, super small, arguably unobservably small, should we have hope to arrive at a theory of quantum gravity somehow?
What are the different ways we can get there?
You've mentioned that you're not as interested in that effort because basically, yes, you cannot have ways to scientifically validate it given the tools of today.
I've actually, you know, I've over the years certainly spent a lot of time learning about gravity and about attempts to quantize it, but it hasn't been that much in the past, the focus of what I've been thinking about.
But I mean, my feeling was always, you know, as I think Spina would agree that the, you know, one way you can pursue this if you can't do experiments is just this kind of search for consistency.
You know, it can be remarkably hard We'll come up with a completely consistent model of this in a way that brings together quantum mechanics and general relativity.
And that's, I think, kind of been the traditional way that people who have pursued quantum gravity have often pursued, you know, We have the best route to finding a consistent theory of quantum gravity.
And string theorists will tell you this.
Other people will tell you it.
It's kind of what people argue about.
But the problem with all of that is that you end up The danger is that you end up with, that everybody could be successful.
Everybody's program for how to find a theory of quantum gravity, you know, ends up with something that is consistent.
And so, in some sense, you could argue this is what happened to the string theorists.
They solved their problem of finding a consistent theory of quantum gravity, but they found 10 to the 500 solutions.
So if you believe that everything that they would like to be true is true, well, okay, you've got a theory, but it ends up being kind of useless because it's just one of such an infinite number of things which you have no way to experimentally distinguish.
And so this is just a depressing situation.
But I do think that there is a, so again, I think pursuing ideas about what, more about beauty and how can you integrate and unify these issues about gravity with other things we know about physics and can you find a theory where these fit together in a way that makes sense and hopefully predict something that's much more promising.
Well, it makes sense, and hopefully, I mean, we'll sneak up onto this question a bunch of times, because you kind of said a few slightly contradictory things, which is like, it's nice to have a theory that's consistent, but then if the theory is consistent, it doesn't necessarily mean anything.
So like... It's not enough, it's not enough.
It's not enough, and that's the problem, so it's like it keeps coming back to, okay, there should be some experimental validation.
So, okay, let's talk a little bit about string theory.
You've been a bit of an outspoken critic of string theory.
Maybe one question first to ask is, what is string theory?
And beyond that, why is it wrong?
Or rather, as the title of your blog says, not even wrong.
Okay. One interesting thing about the current state of string theory is that I'd argue it's actually very, very difficult at this point to say what string theory means.
If people say they're string theorists, what they mean and what they're doing is kind of hard to pin down the meaning of the term.
But the initial meaning, I think, goes back to there was kind of a series of developments starting in 1984 in which people felt that they had found a unified theory of Of our so-called standard model of all the standard, well-known kind of particle interactions and gravity, and it all fit together in a quantum theory, and that you could do this in a very specific way by, instead of thinking about I think a quantum theory of particles moving around in space-time.
Think about quantum theory of one-dimensional loops moving around in space-time, so-called strings.
And so instead of one degree of freedom, these have an infinite number of degrees of freedom.
It's a much more complicated theory, but you can imagine Okay, we're going to quantize this theory of loops moving around in space-time.
And what they found is that you could do this and you could fairly, relatively straightforwardly make sense of such a quantum theory, but only if space and time together were 10-dimensional.
Okay. And so then you had this problem, again, the problem I referred to at the beginning of, okay, now once you make that move, you've got to get rid of six dimensions.
And so the hope was that you could get rid of the six dimensions by making them very small, and that consistency of the theory would require that these six dimensions satisfy a very specific condition called being a Calabi-Au manifold, and that We knew very, very few examples of this.
So what got a lot of people very excited back in 84, 85 was the hope that you could just take this 10-dimensional string theory and find one of a limited number of possible ways of getting rid of six dimensions by making them small, and then you would end up with an effective four-dimensional theory which looked like the real world.
This was the hope. So then there's a very long story about what happened to that hope over the years.
I mean, I would argue, and part of the point of the book and its title was that this ultimately was a failure, that this idea just didn't—there ended up being just too many ways of doing this, and you didn't know how to do this consistently.
It was kind of— Not even wrong in the sense that you never could pin it down well enough to actually get a real falsifiable prediction out of it that would tell you it was wrong.
But it was kind of in the realm of ideas which initially look good, but the more you look at them, they don't work out the way you want, and they don't actually end up carrying the power that you originally had this vision of.
And yes, the book title is not even wrong.
Your blog, your excellent blog title is not even wrong.
Okay, but there's nevertheless been a lot of excitement about string theory through the decades, as you mentioned.
What are the different flavors of ideas that came, like, that branched out?
You mentioned 10 dimensions, you mentioned loops with infinite degrees of freedom.
What other interesting ideas to you that kind of emerged from this world?
Well, yeah, I mean, the problem with talking about the whole subject, and partly the only reason I wrote the book, is that it gets very, very complicated.
I mean, there's a huge amount, you know, a lot of people got very interested in this, a lot of people worked on it, and in some sense, I think what happened is exactly because the idea didn't really work, That this caused people to, you know, instead of focusing on this one idea and digging in and working on that, they just kind of kept trying new things.
And so people, I think, ended up wandering around in a very, very rich space of ideas about mathematics and physics and discovering, you know, all sorts of really interesting things.
It's just the problem is there tended to be an inverse relationship between how interesting and beautiful and fruitful this new idea that they were trying to pursue was and how much it looked like the real world.
So there's a lot of beautiful mathematics came out of it.
I think one of the most spectacular is what the physicists call two-dimensional conformal field theory.
And so these are basically...
Quantum field theories and kind of think of it as one space and one time dimension, which have just this huge amount of symmetry and a huge amount of structure, which is just some totally fantastic mathematics behind it.
And again, some of that mathematics is exactly also what appears in the Langlands program.
So a lot of the first interaction between math and physics around the Langlands program has been around these two-dimensional conformal field theories.
Is there something you could say about what the major problems are with string theory?
Besides that there's no experimental validation, you've written that a big hole in string theory has been its perturbative definition.
Perhaps that's one.
Can you explain what that means? Well, maybe to begin with, I think the simplest thing to say is The initial idea really was that, okay, we have this, instead of what's great is we have this thing that only works, that's very structured and has to work in a certain way for it to make sense.
But then you ended up in 10 space-time dimensions.
And so to get back to physics, you had to get rid of five of the dimensions, six of the dimensions.
And the bottom line, I would say, in some sense, is very simple, that what people just discovered is just, There's kind of no particularly nice way of doing this.
There's an infinite number of ways of doing it, and you can get whatever you want depending on how you do it.
So you end up, the whole program of starting at 10 dimensions and getting to four just kind of collapses out of a lack of any way to kind of get to where you want because you can get anything.
The hope around that problem has always been that The standard formulation that we have of string theory, which is, you can go by the name perturbative, but it's kind of, there's a standard way we know of given a classical theory of constructing a quantum theory and working with it, which is the so-called perturbation theory.
That we know how to do, and that That by itself just doesn't give you any hint as to what to do about the six dimensions.
So actual perturbed with string theory by itself really only works in ten dimensions.
So you have to start making some kinds of assumptions about how I'm going to go beyond this formulation that we really understand of string theory and get rid of these six dimensions.
So kind of the simplest one was the Klabiau postulate.
But when that didn't really work out, people have tried more and more different things.
And the hope has always been that The solution to this problem would be that you would find a deeper and better understanding of what string theory is that would actually go beyond this perturbative expansion, which would generalize this.
And that once you had that, it would solve this problem of, it would pick out what to do with the six dimensions.
How difficult is this problem?
If I could restate the problem, it seems like there's a very consistent physical world operating in four dimensions.
And how do you map a consistent physical world in 10 dimensions to a consistent physical world in four dimensions?
And how difficult is this problem?
Is that something you can even answer?
Just in terms of physics, intuition, in terms of mathematics, mapping from 10 dimensions to four dimensions.
Well, basically, I mean, you have to get rid of six of the dimensions.
So there's kind of two ways of doing it.
One is what we call compactification.
You say that there really are 10 dimensions, but for whatever reason, six of them are so, so small, we can't see them.
So you basically start out with 10 dimensions and what we call, you know, make six of them Not go out to infinity, but just kind of a finite extent and then make that size go down so small it's unobservable.
That's a math trick.
So can you also help me build an intuition about how rich and interesting the world in those six dimensions is?
So compactification seems to imply that it's not very interesting.
But the problem is that what you learn if you start doing mathematics and looking at geometry and topology and more and more dimensions is that, I mean, asking the question like, what are all possible six-dimensional spaces?
It's kind of an unanswerable question.
I mean, it's even kind of technically undecidable in some way.
There are too many things you can do with all these If you start trying to make one-dimensional spaces, it's like, well, you've got a line, you can make a circle, you can make graphs, you can kind of see what you can do.
But as you go to higher and higher dimensions, there are just so many ways you can put things together and get something of that dimensionality.
Unless you have some very, very strong principle, which is going to pick out some very specific Ones of these six-dimensional spaces, and there are just too many of them, and you can get anything you want.
So if you have ten dimensions...
The kind of things that happen, say that's actually the way, that's actually the fabric of our reality's 10 dimensions.
There's a limited set of behaviors of objects, I don't even know what the right terminology to use, that can occur within those dimensions, like in reality.
And so what I'm getting at is like, is there some consistent constraints So if you have some constraints that map to reality, then you could start saying like, dimension number seven is kind of boring.
All the excitement happens in the spatial dimensions, one, two, three.
And time is also kind of boring.
Some are more exciting than others.
Or we can use our metric of beauty.
Some dimensions are more beautiful than others.
Once you have an actual understanding of what actually happens in those dimensions in our physical world, as opposed to sort of all the possible things that could happen.
In some sense, just the basic fact is you need to get rid of them.
We don't see them. So you need to somehow explain them.
The main thing you're trying to do is to explain why we're not seeing them.
And so you have to come up with some theory of these extra dimensions and how they're going to behave.
And string theory gives you some ideas about how to do that.
But the bottom line is where you're trying to go with this whole theory you're creating is to just make all of its effects essentially unobservable.
So it's not a really...
It's an inherently kind of dubious and worrisome thing that you're trying to do there.
Why are you just adding in all this stuff and then trying to explain why we don't see it?
This may be a dumb question, but is this an obvious thing to state that those six dimensions are unobservable or anything beyond four dimensions is unobservable?
Or do you leave a little door open to saying the current tools of physics, and obviously our brains are unable to observe them, but we may need to come up with methodologies for observing them.
So as opposed to collapsing your mathematical theory into four dimensions, leaving the door open a little bit to maybe we need to come up with tools that actually allow us to directly measure those dimensions.
Yes, I mean, you can certainly ask, you know, assume that we've got a model, look at models with more dimensions and ask, you know, what would be observable effects?
How would we know this?
And then you go out and do experiments.
So, for instance, you have a, like, gravitationally, you have an inverse square law of forces.
Okay, if you had more dimensions, that inverse square law would change to something else.
So you can go and start measuring the inverse square law and say, okay, inverse square law is working, but maybe if I get...
And it turns out to be actually kind of very, very hard to measure gravitational effects at even kind of somewhat macroscopic distances because they're so small.
So you can start looking at the inverse square law and say, start trying to measure it at shorter and shorter distances and see if there were extra dimensions at those distance scales, you would start to see the inverse square law fail.
And so people look for that.
And again, you don't see it, but you can, I mean, there's all sorts of experiments of this kind.
You can imagine which test for effects of extra dimensions at different distance scales, but none of them I mean, they all just don't work.
Nothing yet. But you can say, ah, but it's just much, much smaller.
You can say that. Which, by the way, makes LIGO. And the detection of gravitational waves is quite an incredible project.
Yeah. Ed Witten is often brought up as one of the most brilliant mathematicians and physicists ever.
What do you make of him and his work on string theory?
Well, I think he's a truly remarkable figure.
I had the pleasure of meeting him first when he was a postdoc.
He's a completely amazing mathematician and physicist.
He's quite a bit smarter than any of the rest of us and also more hardworking.
It's a frightening combination to see how much he's been able to do.
But I would actually argue that his greatest work, the things that he's done that have been of just this mind-blowing significance of giving us...
I mean, he's completely revolutionized some areas of mathematics.
He's totally revolutionized the way we understand the relations between mathematics and physics.
And most of those, his greatest work, is stuff that has little or nothing to do with string theory.
For instance, he was actually one of the fields.
The very strange thing about him in some sense is that he doesn't have a Nobel Prize, so there's a very large number of people who are nowhere near as smart as he is and don't work anywhere near as hard who have Nobel Prizes.
I think he just had the misfortune of coming into the field at a time when things had gotten much, much, much tougher and nobody really had...
No matter how smart you were, it would have been very hard to come up with a new idea that was going to work physically and get you a Nobel Prize.
But he got a Fields Medal for certain work he did in mathematics, and that's just completely unheard of, you know, for mathematicians to give a Fields Medal to someone outside their field, and physics is really...
You know, you wouldn't have before he came around.
I don't think anybody would have thought that was even conceivable.
So you're saying he came into the field of theoretical physics at a time when, and still to today, is you can't get a Nobel Prize for purely theoretical work.
The specific problem of trying to do better than the standard, the standard model is just this insanely successful thing, and it kind of came together in 1973, pretty much.
And all of the people who kind of were involved in that coming together, many of them ended up with Nobel Prizes for that.
But if you look post-1973, pretty much, it's a little bit more, there's some edge cases, if you like, but if you look post-1973 at what people have done to try to do better than the standard model and to get a better, you know, idea, it really hasn't, it's been too hard a problem.
It hasn't worked. The theory's too good.
So it's not that other people went out there and did it, and not him, and that they got Nobel Prizes for doing it.
The kind of thing he's been trying to do with string theory, no one has been able to do since 1973.
Is there something you can say about the standard model, so the four laws of physics that seems to work very well, and yet people are striving to do more?
Talking about unification and so on, why?
What's wrong, what's broken about the standard model?
Why does it need to be improved?
I mean, the thing that gets most attention is gravity, that we have trouble.
So you want to, in some sense, integrate Integrate what we know about the gravitational force with it and have a unified quantum field theory that has gravitational interactions also.
So that's the big problem everybody talks about.
But it's also true that if you look at the standard model, it has these very, very deep, beautiful ideas, but there's certain aspects of it that are very...
Let's just say that they're not beautiful.
To make the thing work, you have to throw in lots and lots of extra parameters at various points.
And a lot of this has to do with the so-called Higgs mechanism in the Higgs field.
That if you look at the theory, everything is...
If you forget about the Higgs field and what it needs to do, the rest of the theory is...
It's very, very constrained and has very, very few free parameters, really, a very small number.
There's a very small number of parameters and a few integers which tell you what the theory is.
To make this work as a theory of the real world, you need a Higgs field and it needs to do something.
Once you introduce that Higgs field, all sorts of parameters make an appearance.
So now we've got 20 or 30 or whatever parameters that are going to tell you what all the masses of things are and what's going to happen.
So you've gone from a very tightly constrained thing with a couple parameters to this thing which the minute you put it in, you had to add all these extra parameters to make things work.
And so that It may be one argument as well, that's just the way the world is, and the fact that you don't find that aesthetically pleasing is just your problem, or maybe we live in a multiverse and those numbers are just different in every universe.
But, you know, another reasonable conjecture is just that, well, this is just telling us
that there's something we don't understand about what's going on in a deeper way, which
would explain those numbers.
And there's some kind of deeper idea about where the Higgs field comes from and what's
going on, which we haven't figured out yet, and that that's what we should look for.
To stick on string theory a little bit longer, could you play devil's advocate and try to argue for string theory, why it is something that deserved the effort that it got and still, like if you think of it as a flame, still should be a little flame that keeps burning?
Well, I think the most positive argument for it is all sorts of new ideas about mathematics and about parts of physics really emerged from it.
So it was a very fruitful source of ideas.
And I think this is actually one argument you'll definitely, which I kind of agree with,
I'll hear from Witten and from other string theorists, that this is just such a fruitful
and inspiring idea, and it's led to so many other different things coming out of it that
there must be something right about this. And that's, yeah, okay, that, anyway, I think that's
probably the strongest thing that they've got.
But you don't think there's aspects to it that could be neighboring to a theory that does unify everything, to a theory of everything?
It may not be exactly...
Exactly the theory, but sticking on it longer might get us closer to the theory of everything.
The problem with it now, really, is that you really don't know what it is now.
Nobody has ever kind of come up with this non-perturbative theory.
So it's become more and more frustrating and an odd activity to try to argue with a string theorist about string theory, because it's become less and less well-defined what it is.
And it's become actually more and more kind of a...
You have this weird phenomenon of people calling themselves string theorists when they've never actually worked on any theory where there are any strings anywhere.
So what has actually happened kind of sociologically is that You started out with this fairly well-defined proposal, and then I would argue because that didn't work, people branched out in all sorts of directions doing all sorts of things that became farther and farther removed from that.
And for sociological reasons, the ones who kind of started out Or were trained by the people who worked on that, have now become this string theorist.
But it's become almost more kind of a tribal denominator.
So it's very hard to know what you're arguing about when you're arguing about string theory these days.
Well, to push back on that a little bit, I mean, string theory, it's just a term, right?
It doesn't, like you could, like this is the way language evolves, is it could start to represent something more than just the theory that involves strings.
It could represent the effort to unify the laws of physics, right?
At high dimensions with these super tiny objects, right?
Or something like that. I mean, we can sort of put string theory aside.
So for example, in neural networks in the space of machine learning, there was a time when they were extremely popular.
They became much, much less popular to a point where if you mention neural networks, you're getting no funding and you're not going to be respected at conferences.
And then once again, Neural networks became all the rage about 10, 15 years ago.
And it goes up and down.
And a lot of people would argue that using terminology like machine learning and deep learning is often misused, overgeneral.
Everything that works is deep learning.
Everything that doesn't isn't.
Yeah. Something like that. You know, that's just the way, again, we're back to sociological things.
But I guess what I'm trying to get at is if we leave the sociological mess aside, do we throw out the baby with the bathwater?
Is there some, besides the side effects of nice ideas from the Ed Wittons of the world, Is there some core truths there that we should stick by in the full beautiful mess of a space that we call string theory, that people call string theory?
You're right. It is kind of a common problem that, you know, how what you call some field changes and evolves in interesting ways as the field changes.
But, I mean, I guess what I would argue is the initial understanding of string theory that was quite specific, we're talking about a specific idea, 10-dimensional, super-strings, compactified in six dimensions.
To my mind, the really bad thing that's happened to the subject is that it's hard to get people to admit, at least publicly, that that was a failure, that this really didn't work.
And so, de facto, what people do is people stop doing that and they start doing more interesting things, but they keep talking to the public about string theory and referring back to that idea and using that as kind of the starting point and as kind of the place where the Where the whole tribe starts and everything comes from.
So the problem with this is that having as your initial name and what everything points back to something which really didn't work out, it kind of makes everybody, it makes everything, you've created this potentially very, very interesting field with interesting things happening, but You know, people in graduate school take courses on string theory and everything kind of, and this is what you tell the public in which you're continually pointing back.
So you're continually pointing back to this idea which never worked out as your guiding inspiration.
And it really kind of deforms your whole way of your hopes of making progress.
And that's, to me, I think, you know, the kind of worst thing that's happened in this field.
Yeah. Okay, sure. So there's a lack of transparency and sort of authenticity about communicating the things that failed in the past.
And so you don't have a clear picture of like firm ground that you're standing on.
But again, those are sociological things.
There's a bunch of questions I want to ask you.
So one, what's your intuition about Why the original idea failed.
So what can you say about why you're pretty sure it has failed?
The initial idea was, as I tried to explain it, it was quite seductive in that you could see why Witten and others got excited by it.
It was... At the time, it looked like there were only a few of these possible clabeas that would work, and it looked like, okay, we just have to understand this very specific model and these very specific six-dimensional spaces, and we're going to get everything.
And so it was a very subjective idea.
But it just, as people...
Learned, worked more and more about it.
It just didn't, they just kind of realized that there are just more and more things you can do with these six dimensions and you can't, and this is just not going to work.
Meaning like it's, I mean, what was the failure mode here?
Is you could just have an infinite number of possibilities that you could do so you can come up with any theory you want.
You can fit quantum mechanics.
You can explain gravity.
You can explain anything you want with it.
Is that the basic failure mode?
Yeah, so it's a failure mode of kind of that this idea ended up being essentially empty.
It just ends up not telling you anything because it's consistent with just about anything.
If you try and talk with string theorists about this now, there's a long argument over this about whether...
You know, oh, no, no, no, maybe there still are constraints coming out of this idea or not.
Or maybe we live in a multiverse and, you know, everything is true anyway.
So you can, there are various ways you can kind of, the string theorists have kind of react to this kind of argument that I'm making.
Try to hold on to it.
What about experimental validation?
Is that a fair standard to hold before a theory of everything that's trying to unify quantum mechanics and gravity?
Yeah, I mean, ultimately, to be really convinced that some new idea about unification really works, you need to look at the real world and see that this is telling you something true about it.
I mean, either Telling you that if you do some experiment and go out and do it, you'll get some unexpected result, and that's the kind of gold standard.
Or it may be just like all those numbers that we don't know how to explain, it will show you how to calculate them.
I mean, it can be various kinds of experimental validation, but that's certainly ideally what you're looking for.
How tough is this, do you think, for a theory of everything, not just string theory, for something that unifies gravity and quantum mechanics, so the very big and the very small?
Let me ask you one way.
Is it a physics problem, a math problem, or an engineering problem?
My guess is that it's a combination of a physics and a math problem that you really need It's not really interesting.
It's not like there's some kind of well-defined thing you can write down and we just don't have enough computer power to do the calculation.
That's not the kind of problem it is at all.
But the question is, you know, what mathematical tools you need to properly formulate the problem.
It is unclear.
So one reasonable conjecture is the reason that we haven't had any success yet is just that either we're missing certain physical ideas or we're missing certain mathematical tools, or some combination of them, which we need to kind of properly formulate the problem and see that it has a solution that looks like the real world.
Yeah. I guess you don't, but there's a sense that you need both gravity, like all the laws of physics to be operating on the same level.
So it feels like you need an object like a black hole or something like that.
In order to make predictions about, otherwise you're always making predictions about this joint phenomena.
Or can you do that as long as the theory is consistent and doesn't have special cases for each of the phenomena?
Well, your theory should, I mean, if your theory is gonna include gravity, our current understanding of gravity is that you should have There should be black hole states in it.
You should be able to describe black holes in this theory.
And just one aspect that people have concentrated a lot on is just this kind of questions about if your theory includes black holes like it's supposed to and it includes quantum mechanics, then there's certain kind of paradoxes which come up.
And so that's been a huge focus of quantum gravity work has been just those paradoxes.
So stepping outside of string theory, can you just say first at a high level, what is the theory of everything?
What is the theory of everything seek to accomplish?
Well, I mean, this is very much a kind of reductionist point of view in the sense that, so it's not a theory.
This is not going to explain to you, you know, anything.
It doesn't really, this kind of theory, this kind of theory of everything we're talking about doesn't say anything interesting, particularly about like macroscopic objects, about what the weather's going to be tomorrow or, you know, things are happening at this scale.
But just what we've discovered is that as you look at, um, You can start breaking it apart and you end up with some fairly simple pieces, quanta if you like, which are interacting in some fairly simple way.
What we mean by the theory of everything is a theory that describes all All the correct objects you need to describe what's happening in the world and describes how they're interacting with each other at a most fundamental level.
How you get from that theory to describing some macroscopic, incredibly complicated thing is there that becomes, again, more of an engineering problem.
You may need machine learning or you may need a lot of very different things to do it.
Well, I don't even think it's just engineering.
It's also science. One thing that I find...
Kind of interesting.
Talking to physicists is a little bit There's a little bit of hubris.
Some of the most brilliant people I know are physicists, both philosophy and just in terms of mathematics, in terms of understanding the world.
But there's a kind of either a hubris or what would I call it?
Like a confidence that if we have a theory of everything, we will understand everything.
Like this is the deepest thing to understand.
And I would say, and like the rest is details, right?
That's the old Rutherford thing.
But to me, this is like a cake or something.
There's layers to this thing and each one has a theory of everything.
Like at every level from biology, like how life originates.
That itself, like complex systems.
That in itself is like this gigantic thing that requires a theory of everything.
And then there's the, in the space of humans, psychology, like intelligence, collective intelligence, the way it emerges among species.
That feels like a complex system that requires its own theory of everything.
On top of that is things like in the computing space, artificial intelligence systems, like that feels like it needs a theory of everything.
And it's almost like once we solve, once we come up with a theory of everything that explains the basic laws of physics that gave us the universe, Even stuff that's super complex, like how the universe might be able to originate.
Even explaining something that you're not a big fan of, like multiverses or stuff that we don't have any evidence of yet.
Still, we won't be able to have a strong explanation Of why food tastes delicious.
Yeah, I agree completely.
There is something completely wrong with this terminology of theory of everything.
It's really, in some sense, very hubristic and bad terminology because it's not.
This is explaining This is a purely kind of reductionist point of view that you're trying to understand certain very specific kind of things, which, in principle, other things emerge from, but to actually understand how anything emerges from this, it can't be understood in terms of This underlying fundamental theory is going to be hopeless in terms of kind of telling you about this various emergent behavior.
And as you go to different levels of explanation, you're going to need to develop completely different ideas, completely different ways of thinking.
Yeah. I guess there's a famous kind of Phil Anderson's slogan is that, you know, more is different.
And so it's just, you know, even once you understand how, what a couple of things, if you have a collection of stuff and you understand perfectly well how each thing is interacting with the others, what the whole thing is going to do is just a completely different problem.
And you need completely different ways of thinking about it.
What do you think about this?
I got to ask you at a few different attempts at a theory of everything, especially recently.
So I've been, for many years, a big fan of cellular automata of complex systems.
And obviously, because of that, a fan of Stephen Wolfram's work in that space.
But he's recently been talking about a theory of everything through his physics project, essentially.
What do you think about this kind of discrete Theory of everything.
Like, from simple rules and simple objects and hypergraphs emerges all of our reality, where time and space are emergent.
Basically, everything we see around us is emergent.
Yeah, I have to say, unfortunately, I have kind of pretty much zero sympathy for that.
I mean, I don't... I spent a little time looking at it, and I just don't see—it doesn't seem to me to get anywhere.
And it really is—just really, really doesn't agree at all with what I'm seeing, this kind of unification of math and physics that I'm kind of talking about around certain kinds of very deep ideas about geometry and stuff.
If you want to believe that your things are really coming out of cellular automata at the most fundamental level, you have to believe that everything that I've seen my whole career as beautiful, powerful ideas, that that's all just kind of a mirage, which just kind of randomly is emerging from these more basic, very, very simple-minded things.
And You have to give me some serious evidence for that, and I'm saying nothing.
So, Mirage, you don't think there could be a consistency where things like quantum mechanics could emerge from much, much, much smaller, discrete computational-type systems?
Well, I think from the point of view of a certain mathematical point of view, quantum mechanics is already mathematically as simple as it gets.
It really is A story about really the fundamental objects that you work with when you write down a quantum theory are, in some point of view, precisely the fundamental objects at the deepest levels of mathematics that you're working with.
They're exactly the same.
And cellular automata are something completely different which don't fit into these structures.
And so I just don't see why.
Anyway, I don't see it as a promising...
You know, probably the same thing to do.
And then just looking at it and seeing, does this go anywhere?
Does this solve any problem that I've ever, that I didn't, does this solve any problem of any kind?
I just don't see it. Yeah, to me cellular automata and these hypergraphs, I'm not sure solving a problem is even the standard to apply here at this moment.
To me, the fascinating thing is that the question it asks have no good answers.
So there's not good math explaining, forget the physics of it, math explaining the behavior of complex systems.
And that to me is both exciting and paralyzing.
Like we're at the very early days of understanding You know, how complicated and fascinating things emerge from simple rules.
Yeah. You know, I agree.
I think that is a truly great problem.
And depending where it goes, it may be, you know, it may start to develop some kind of connections to the things that I've kind of found more fruitful and It's hard to know.
I think a lot of that area I strongly feel I best not say too much about it because I don't know too much about it.
Again, we're back to this original problem that your time in life is...
It's limited. You have to figure out what you're gonna spend your time thinking about, and that's something I've just never seen enough to convince me to spend more time thinking about.
Well, also timing. It's not just that our time is limited, but the timing of the kind of things you think about.
There's some aspect to cellular automata, these kinds of objects, that it feels like we're very many years away from having big breakthroughs on.
And so it's like, you have to pick the problems that are solvable today.
In fact, my intuition, again, perhaps biased, is it feels like the kind of systems that, complex systems that cellular automata are, would not be solved by human brains.
It feels like something post-human that will solve that problem, or like significantly enhanced humans, meaning like using computational tools, very powerful computational tools to us to crack these problems open.
That's if our approach to science, our ability to understand science, our ability to understand physics will become more and more computational, or there'll be a whole field that's computational in nature, which currently is not the case.
Currently, computation is the thing that sort of Assists us in understanding science the way we've been doing it all along.
But if there's a whole new, I mean, we're from new kind of science, right?
It's a little bit dramatic.
But, you know, if computers could do science on their own, computational systems, perhaps that's the way they would do the science.
They would try to understand the cellular automata.
And that feels like we're decades away.
So perhaps you'll crack open some interesting facets of this physics problem, but it's very far away.
So timing is everything.
That's perfectly possible, yeah.
Well, let me ask you then in the space of geometry, I don't know how well you know Eric Weinstein.
Oh, quite well, yeah. What are your thoughts about his geometric unity and the space of ideas that he's playing with in his proposal for Theory of Everything?
Well, I think that he fundamentally has, I think, the same problems that everybody has had trying to do this.
And they're really versions of the same problem that you try to...
You try to get unity by putting everything into some bigger structure.
So he has some other ones that are not so conventional that he's trying to work with.
But he has the same problem that even if he can get a lot farther in terms of having a
really well-defined, well-understood, clear picture of these things he's working with,
they're really kind of large geometrical structures of many dimensions, many kinds.
And I just don't see any way he's going to have the same problem the string theorists
have.
It's really down to the structures of the standard model and how do you...
Yeah, so I just...
Anyway, it's the same.
And there's another interesting example of a similar kind of thing is Garrett Lisey's
theory of everything.
Again, you know, there it's a little bit more specific than Eric's.
He's working with this E8, but it, again, I think all these things founder at the same point that you don't, You create this unity, but then you don't actually have a good idea how you're going to get back to the actual To the objects we've seen, you create these big symmetries, how are you going to break them?
Because we don't see those symmetries in the real world.
So ultimately, there would need to be a simple process for collapsing it to four dimensions.
You'd have to explain it. Well, yeah, I forget in his case, but it's not just four dimensions.
It's also these... These structures you see in the standard model, there's certain very small-dimensional groups of symmetries called U1, SU2, and SU3. And this has been the problem since the beginning.
Almost immediately after 1973, about a year later, two years later, people started talking about grand unified theories.
So you take the U1, the SU2, and the SU3, and you put them together into this bigger structure called the SU5 or SO10. But then you're stuck with this problem that, wait a minute, why does the world not look, why do I not see these SU5 symmetries in the world?
I only see these. And I think, you know, the kind of thing that Eric and all of a sudden Garrett and lots of people try to do, they all kind of founder in that same way, that they don't have a good answer to that.
Are there lessons, ideas to be learned from theories like that, from Garrett Lease's, from Eric's?
I don't know, it depends. I have to confess, I haven't looked that closely at Eric's.
I mean, he explained this to me personally a few times, and I've looked a bit at his paper, but it's, again, we're back to the problem of a limited amount of time in life.
Yeah, I mean, it's an interesting effect, right?
Why don't more physicists look at it?
They're... I mean, I'm in this position that somehow, you know, people write me emails for whatever reason.
And I worked in the space of AI. And so there's a lot of people, perhaps AI is even way more accessible than physics in a certain sense.
And so a lot of people write to me with different theories about what they have for how to create general intelligence.
And it's, again, a little bit of an excuse I say to myself, like, well, I only have a limited amount of time, so that's why I'm not investigating it.
But I wonder if there's ideas out there that are still powerful, they're still fascinating, and that I'm missing because I'm dismissing them because they're outside of the sort of the usual process of academic research.
Yeah, well, I mean, the same thing pretty much every day in my email, somebody's got a theory of everything about why all of what physicists are doing.
Perhaps the most disturbing thing I should say about my being a critic of string theory is that when you realize who your fans are, that every day I hear from somebody who says, oh, well, since you don't like string theory, you must, of course, agree with me that this is the right way to think about everything.
Oh, no. Oh, no.
And, you know, most of these are, you know, you quickly can see this person doesn't know very much and doesn't know what they're doing.
You know, but there's a whole continuum to, you know, people who are quite serious physicists and mathematicians who are making a fairly serious attempt to try to do something, like Garrett and Eric.
And then your problem is...
You do try to spend more time looking at it and trying to figure out what they're really doing, but at some point you just realize, wait a minute, for me to really, really understand exactly what's going on here would just...
Take time I just don't have.
Yeah, it takes a long time.
Which is the nice thing about AI, is unlike the kind of physics we're talking about, if your idea is good, that should quite naturally lead to you being able to build a system that's intelligent.
So you don't need to get approval from somebody that's saying you have a good idea here.
You can just utilize that idea and engineer a system.
Like naturally leads to engineering.
With physics here, if you have a perfect theory that explains everything, that still doesn't obviously lead one to...
One to scientific experiments that can validate that theory, and two to trinkets you can build and sell at a store for five dollars.
You can't make money off of it. So that makes it much more challenging.
Well, let me also ask you about something that you found especially recently appealing, which is Roger Penrose's Twister Theory.
What is it? What kind of questions might it allow us to answer?
What will the answers look like?
It's only in the last couple of years that I've really, really kind of come to really, I think, to appreciate it and to see how to really, I believe, to see how to really do something with it.
And I've gotten very excited about that the last year or two.
I mean, one way of saying...
One idea of Twister theory is that it's a different way of thinking about what space and time are and about what points in space and time are, which is very interesting that it only really works in four dimensions.
So four dimensions behaves very, very specially, unlike other dimensions.
And in four dimensions, there is a way of thinking about Space and time geometry where, as well as just thinking about points in space and time, you can also think about different objects, these so-called twisters.
And then when you do that, you end up with a really interesting insight that the That you can formulate a theory, take a standard theory that we formulate in terms of points of space and time, and you can reformulate in this twister language.
And in this twister language, the fundamental objects are actually spheres, in some sense, kind of the light cones.
So maybe one way to say it, which actually I think is really...
It's quite amazing. If you ask yourself, what do we know about the world?
We have this idea that the world out there is all these different points.
Well, that's kind of a derived quantity.
What we really know about the world is when we open our eyes, what do you see?
You see a sphere.
And what you're looking at is you're looking at a sphere's worth of light rays coming into your eyes.
And what Penrose says is that Well, what a point in spacetime is, is that sphere, that sphere of all the light rays coming in.
And he says, and you should formulate your, instead of thinking about points, you should think about the space of those spheres, if you like, and formulate the degrees of freedom as physics as living on those spheres, living on, so you're kind of living on, your degrees of freedom are living on light rays, not on points.
And it's a very different way of thinking about, About physics.
He and others working with him developed a You know, a beautiful mathematical, beautiful mathematical formalism and a way to go back from forth between our kind of some aspects of our standard way we write these things down and work on the so-called twister space.
And, you know, they, certain things worked out very well, but they ended up, you know, I think kind of stuck by the eighties or nineties that they weren't a little bit like string theory that they, they, um, By using these ideas about twisters, they could develop them in different directions and find all sorts of other interesting things, but they weren't finding any way of doing that that brought them back to kind of new insights into physics.
What's kind of gotten me excited, really, is what I think.
I have an idea about that I think does actually work, that goes more in that direction.
I can go on about that endlessly or talk a little bit about it, but that's the...
I think that's the one kind of easy to explain insight about twister theory.
There are some more technical ones.
I think it's also very convincing what it tells you about spinners, for instance, but that's some more technical.
Well, first, let's like linger on the spheres and the light cones.
You're saying Twisted Theory allows you to make that the fundamental object with which you're operating.
Yeah. I mean, first of all, philosophically, that's weird and beautiful.
Maybe because it feels like it moves us so much closer to the way human brains perceive reality.
Yeah. So it's almost like...
Our perception is, like, the content of our perception is the fundamental object of reality.
That's very appealing.
Is it mathematically powerful?
Can you say a little bit more about what the heck that even means?
Because it's much easier to think about mathematically like a point in space-time.
What does it mean to be operating on the light cone?
It uses a kind of mathematics that goes back to the 19th century among mathematicians.
Anyway, it's a bit of a long story, but one problem is that you have to start...
It's crucial that you think in terms of complex numbers and not just real numbers.
And this, for most people, that makes it harder to...
For mathematicians, that's fine.
We love doing that. But for most people, that makes it harder to think about.
But I think perhaps the way that there is something you can say very specifically about it In terms of spinners, which I don't know if you want to, I think at some point you want to talk.
What are spinners?
Let's start with spinners, because I think that if we can introduce that, then I can...
By the way, Twister is spelled with an O, and Spinner is spelled with an O as well.
Yes. Okay. In case you want to Google it and look it up, there's very nice Wikipedia pages as a starting point.
I don't know what is a good starting point for Twister 3.
Well, one thing you say about Penrose, I mean, Penrose is actually a very good writer and also a very good draftsman.
He's on drafts. To the extent this is visualizable, he actually has done some very nice drawings.
Yeah. Almost any kind of expository thing you can find him writing is a very good place to start.
He's a remarkable person.
So spinners are something that independently came out of mathematics and out of physics.
And to say where they came out of physics, I mean, what people realized when they started looking at elementary particles like electrons or whatever, that there seemed to be There seemed to be some kind of doubling of the degrees of freedom going on.
If you counted what was there in some sense in the way you would expect it, and when you started doing quantum mechanics and started looking at elementary particles, there seemed to be two degrees of freedom, there not one.
And one way of seeing it was that if you put your electron in a strong magnetic field, And asked what was the energy of it.
Instead of it having one energy, it would have two energies.
It would be two energy levels. And as you increase the field, the splitting would increase.
So physicists kind of realized that, wait a minute.
So we thought when we first started doing quantum mechanics that the way to describe Particles was in terms of wave functions, and these wave functions were complex to complex values.
Well, if we actually look at particles, that's not right.
They're pairs of complex numbers.
They're pairs of complex numbers.
So one of the kind of fundamental, from the physics point of view, the fundamental question is, why are all our kind of fundamental particles...
Described by pairs of complex numbers, which is weird.
And then you can ask, well, what happens if you take an electron and rotate it?
So how do things move in this pair of complex numbers?
Well, now, if you go back to mathematics, what had been understood in mathematics some years earlier, not that many years earlier, was that if you ask very, very generally, think about geometry of three dimensions, and if you think about things that are happening in three dimensions in the standard way, the standard way of doing geometry, everything is about vectors.
If you've taken any mathematics classes, you probably see vectors at some point.
They're just triplets of numbers tell you what a direction is or how far you're going in three-dimensional space.
And most of everything we teach in most standard courses in mathematics is about vectors and things you build out of vectors.
So you express everything about geometry in terms of vectors or how they're changing or how you put two of them together and get planes and Whatever.
But what had been realized early on is that if you ask very, very generally, what are the things that you can kind of consistently think about rotating?
And so you ask a technical question, what are the representations of the rotation group?
Well, you find that one answer is there vectors and everything you build out of vectors.
But then people found, but wait a minute, there's also these other things which you can't build out of vectors, but which you can consistently rotate.
And they're described by pairs of complex numbers, by two complex numbers.
And they're the spinners also.
And you can think of spinners in some sense as more fundamental than vectors, because you can build vectors out of spinners.
You can take two spinners and make a vector.
But if you only have vectors, you can't get spinners.
So there, in some sense, there's some kind of lower level of geometry beyond what we thought it was, which was kind of spinner geometry.
And this is something which, even to this day, when we teach graduate courses in geometry, we mostly don't talk about this because it's a bit hard to do correctly.
If you start with your whole setup as in terms of vectors, Describing things in terms of spinners is a whole different ballgame.
But anyway, it was just this amazing fact that this kind of more fundamental piece of geometry of spinners and what we were actually seeing, if you look at electron, are one and the same.
I think it's kind of a mind-blowing thing, but it's very counterintuitive.
What are some weird properties of spinners that are counterintuitive?
There are some things that they do.
For instance, if you rotate a spinner around 360 degrees, it doesn't come back to where it becomes minus what it was.
Anyway, so the way rotations work, there's a kind of a funny sign you have to keep track of in some sense.
So they're kind of too valued in another weird way.
But the fundamental problem is that it's just not, if you're used to visualizing vectors, there's nothing you can do visualizing in terms of vectors that will ever give you a spinner.
It just is not gonna ever work.
As you were saying that, I was visualizing a vector walking along a Mobius strip, and it ends up being upside down.
But you're saying that doesn't really capture...
So, I mean, what really captures it?
The problem is that it's really...
The simplest way to describe it is in terms of two complex numbers.
And your problem with two complex numbers is that's four real numbers.
So, your spinner kind of lies in a four-dimensional space, so you...
That makes it hard to visualize.
And it's crucial that it's not just any four dimensions.
It's actually complex numbers.
You're really going to use the fact that these are complex numbers.
It's very hard to visualize.
But to get back to what I think is mind-blowing about twisters is that another way of saying this idea about talking about spheres, another way of saying the fundamental idea of twister theory is In some sense, the fundamental idea of twister theory is that a point is a two-complex-dimensional space, and that the space that it lies inside is twister space.
So in the simplest case, twister space is four-dimensional, and A point in space-time is a two-complex dimensional subspace of all the four complex dimensions.
And as you move around in space-time, your planes are just moving around.
So it's a plane in a four-dimensional space?
It's a plane.
Complex. Complex plane.
So it's two complex dimensions in four complex dimensions.
But then, to me, the mind-blowing thing about this is this then kind of tautologically answers the question is, what is a spinner?
Well, a spinner is a point.
I mean, the space of spinners at a point is the point.
In Twister theory, the points are the complex two planes.
And you're asking what a spinner is.
Well, the space of spinners is that two plane.
So it's, you know, just your whole definition of what a point in space-time was just told you what a spinner was.
They're just—it's the same thing.
Yeah, well, we're trying to project that into a three-dimensional space and trying to intuit, but you can't.
Yeah, so the intuition becomes very difficult, but— If you're not using twister theory, you have to kind of go through a certain fairly complicated rigmarole to even describe spinners, to describe electrons.
Whereas using twister theory, it's just completely tautological.
They're just what you want to describe the electron is fundamentally the way you're describing the point in spacetime already.
It's just there. Yeah.
Do you have a hope? You mentioned that you found it appealing recently.
Is it just because of certain aspects of its mathematical beauty, or do you actually have a hope that this might lead to a theory of everything?
Yeah, I mean, I certainly do have such a hope, because what I've found, I think the thing which I've done, which I don't think, as far as I can tell, no one had really looked at from this point of view before, is It has to do with this question of how do you treat time in your quantum theory?
And so there's another long story about how we do quantum theories and about how we treat time in quantum theories, which is a long story.
But the short version of it is that what people have found when you try and write down a quantum theory That it's often a good idea to take your time coordinate, whatever you're using to your time coordinate, and multiply it by the square root of minus one and to make it purely imaginary.
And so all these formulas which you have In your standard theory, if you do that to those, I mean, those formulas have some very strange behavior, and they're kind of singular.
If you ask even some simple questions, you have to take very delicate singular limits in order to get the correct answer, and you have to take them from the right direction, otherwise it doesn't work.
Whereas if you just take time, and if you just put a factor of square root of minus one wherever you see the time coordinate, You end up with much simpler formulas which are much better behaved mathematically.
And what I hadn't really appreciated until fairly recently is also how dramatically that changes the whole structure of the theory.
You end up with a consistent way of talking about these quantum theories, but it has some very different flavor and very different aspects that I hadn't really appreciated.
And in particular, the way symmetries act on it is not at all what I originally had expected.
And so that's the new thing that I think gives you something, is to do this move, which people often think of as just kind of a Kind of a mathematical trick that you're doing to make some formulas work out nicely, but to take that mathematical trick as really fundamental.
And it turns out in Twister theory allows you to simultaneously talk about your usual time and the time times the square root of minus one.
They both fit very nicely into Twister theory.
And you end up with some structures which look a lot like the standard models.
Let me ask you about some Nobel Prizes.
Okay. Do you think there will be...
There was a bet between Michio Kaku and somebody else about...
John Horgan. John Horgan about...
By the way, it made me discover a cool website, longbets.com or.org.
Yeah, yeah. It's cool.
It's cool that you can make a bet with people...
And then check in 20 years later.
I really love it. There's a lot of interesting bets on there.
Yeah. I would love to participate.
But it's interesting to see.
You know, time flies. Yeah.
And you make a bet about what's going to happen in 20 years.
You don't realize 20 years just goes like this.
Yeah, yeah. And then you get to face...
And you get to wonder, like...
What was that person, what was I thinking?
That person 20 years ago is almost like a different person.
What was I thinking back then to think that?
It's interesting. So let me ask you this.
On record, you know, 20 years from now or some number of years from now, do you think there will be a Nobel Prize given for something directly connected to a first broadly theory of everything?
And second, of course, one of the possibilities, one of them, string theory.
String theory, definitely not.
Things have gone...
Yeah. So if you were giving financial advice, you would say not to bet on...
No, do not bet on...
And even... I actually suspect if you ask string theorists that question these days, you're going to get a few of them saying...
I mean, if you'd asked them that question 20 years ago, again, when...
Some of them would have taken you up on it.
And certainly back in 1984, a bunch of them would have said, oh, sure, yeah.
But now I get the impression that even they realize that things are not looking good for that particular idea.
Again, it depends what you mean by string theory, whether...
Maybe the term will evolve to mean something else, which will work out.
But I don't think that's not going to like it to work out.
I still think it's relatively unlikely that you'll have any really successful theory of everything, And the main problem is just the...
It's become so difficult to do experiments at higher energy that we've really lost this ability to kind of get unexpected input from experiment.
And you can, you know, while it's maybe hard to figure out what people's thinking is going to be 20 years from now, looking at...
You know, high-energy particle, high-energy colliders and their technology, it's actually pretty easy to make a pretty accurate guess what you're going to be doing 20 years from now.
And I think actually, I would actually claim that it's pretty clear where you're going to be 20 years from now.
And what it's gonna be is you're gonna have the LHC, you're gonna have a lot more data,
an order of magnitude or more data from the LHC, but at the same energy.
You're not gonna see a higher energy accelerator operating successfully in the next 20 years.
And like maybe machine learning or great data science methodologies
that process that data will not reveal any major shifts in our understanding
of the underlying physics, do you think?
I don't think so.
I mean, I think that field, my understanding is they're starting to make a great use of those techniques,
but it seems to look like it will help them solve certain technical problems
and be able to do things somewhat better, but not completely change
the way they're looking at things.
What do you think about the potential of quantum computers simulating quantum mechanical systems and through that sneak up through simulation?
Sneak up to a deep understanding of the fundamental physics.
The problem there is that that's promising more for this, for, you know, for Phil Anderson's problem that, you know, if you wanna, there's lots and lots of, you know, you take, you start putting together lots and lots of things and we think we know they're pair by pair interactions, but what this thing is gonna do, we don't have any good calculational techniques.
You know, quantum computers may very well give you those.
And so they may, what we think of as kind of strong coupling behavior, we have no good way to calculate.
You know, even though we can write down the theory, we don't know how to calculate anything with any accuracy in it.
The quantum computers may solve that problem.
But the problem is that they, I don't think that they're going to solve the problem, that they help you with the problem of not having the, of knowing what the right underlying theory is.
As somebody who likes experimental validation, let me ask you the perhaps ridiculous sounding, but I don't think it's actually a ridiculous question of, do you think we live in a simulation?
Do you find that thought experiment at all useful or interesting?
Not really. It just doesn't...
Anyway, to me, it doesn't actually lead to any kind of interesting, lead anywhere interesting.
Yeah, to me, so maybe I'll throw a wrench into your thing.
To me, it's super interesting from an engineering perspective.
So if you look at virtual reality systems, the actual question is, How much computation and how difficult is it to construct a world that, like there are several levels here.
One is you won't know the difference.
Our human perception systems and maybe even the tools of physics won't know the difference between the simulated world and the real world.
That's sort of more of a physics question.
The most interesting question to me has more to do with why food tastes delicious, which is how difficult and how much computation is required to construct a simulation where you kind of know it's a simulation at first, but you want to stay there anyway.
And over time, you don't even remember.
Yeah. Well, anyway, I agree.
These are kind of fascinating questions, and they may be very, very relevant to our future as a species, but yeah, they're just very far from anything.
I... So from a physics perspective, it's not useful to you to think, taking a computational perspective to our universe, thinking of it as an information processing system, and then think of it as doing computation, and then you think about the resources required to do that kind of computation and all that kind of stuff.
You could just look at the basic physics and who cares what the computer it's running on is.
Yeah, it just, I mean, the kinds of it mean...
I'm willing to agree that you can get into interesting kinds of questions going down that road, but they're just so different from anything, from what I've found interesting.
Again, I just have to kind of go back to life is too short, and I'm very glad other people are thinking about this, but I just don't see anything I can do with it.
What about space itself?
So I have to ask you about aliens.
Again, something, since you emphasize evidence, do you think there is, how many, do you think there are, and how many intelligent alien civilizations are out there?
I have no idea, but I have certainly, as far as I know, unless the government's covering it up or something, we haven't heard from, we don't have any evidence for such things yet, but there seems to be no There's no particular obstruction why there shouldn't be.
I mean, you work on some fundamental questions about the physics of reality when you look up to the stars.
Do you think about whether somebody's looking back at us?
Actually, I originally got interested in physics.
I actually started out as a kid interested in astronomy, exactly that, and a telescope and whatever that, and certainly read a lot of science fiction and I've thought about that.
I find over the years, I find myself kind of less...
Anyway, less and less interested in that, just because I don't really know what to do with...
I also kind of at some point kind of stopped reading science fiction that much, kind of feeling that there's just too...
that the actual science I was kind of learning about was perfectly kind of weird and fascinating and unusual enough and better than any of the stuff that...
And Isaac Asimov, so why should I? Yeah.
And you can mess with the science much more than the distant science fiction.
The one that exists in our imagination or the one that exists out there among the stars.
Well, you mentioned science fiction.
You've written quite a few book reviews.
I've got to ask you about some books, perhaps, if you don't mind.
Is there one or two books that you would recommend to others, and maybe if you can, what ideas you drew from them?
Either negative recommendations or positive recommendations.
Do not read this book for sure.
Well, I must say, unfortunately, you can go to my website and you can click on book reviews and you can see I've written, read a lot of, I mean, as you can tell from my views about string theory, I'm not a fan of a lot of the kind of popular books about, oh, isn't string theory great?
And Yes, I'm not a fan of a lot of things of that kind.
Can I ask you a quick question on this, a small tangent?
Are you a fan, can you explore the pros and cons of, if I get string theory, sort of science communication, sort of Cosmos style, Communication of concepts to people that are outside of physics, outside of mathematics, outside of even the sciences, and helping people to sort of dream and fill them with awe about the full range of mysteries in our universe.
That's a complicated issue. You know, I think, you know, I certainly go back and go back to like what inspired me and maybe to connect it a little bit to this question about books.
I mean, certainly one of the books that some books that I remember reading when I was a kid were about the early history of quantum mechanics, like Heisenberg's books that he wrote about, you know, kind of looking back at telling the history of what happened when he developed quantum mechanics.
It's just kind of a totally fascinating romantic book.
Great story. And those were very inspirational to me.
And I would think maybe other people might also find them.
And that's almost like the human story of the development of the ideas.
Yeah, the human story.
But yeah, just also how, you know, these very, very weird ideas that didn't seem to make sense, how they were struggling with them and how, you know, they actually...
Anyway, I think it's the period of physics kind of beginning, you know, 1905, with Planck and Einstein and ending up with the war when these things get used to, you know, make passively destructive weapons.
It's just totally amazing.
So many new ideas.
Let me on another tangent on top of a tangent on top of a tangent ask, if we didn't have Einstein, so how does science progress?
Is it the lone geniuses or is it some kind of weird network of ideas swimming in the air and just kind of the geniuses pop up to catch them and others would anyway?
Without Einstein, would we have special relativity, general relativity?
I mean, it's an interesting case-to-case basis.
I mean, special relativity, I think we would have had...
I mean, there are other people...
You could even argue that it was already there in some form.
But I think special relativity you would have had without Einstein fairly quickly.
General relativity, that was a much, much harder thing to do and required much more effort, much more sophisticated.
I think you would have had sooner or later, but it would have taken quite a bit longer.
That took a bunch of years to validate scientifically the general relativity.
But even for Einstein, from, you know, the point which he had kind of a general idea of what he was trying to do to the point where he actually had a well-defined theory that you could actually compare to the real world, that was, you know, I forget the numbers, but the order of magnitude 10 years of very serious work.
And if he hadn't been...
It would have taken a while before anyone else got around to it.
On the other hand, there are things like with quantum mechanics, you have Heisenberg and Schrodinger came up with two, which ultimately equivalent, but two different approaches to it within months of each other.
And so if Heisenberg hadn't been there, you already would have had Schrodinger or whatever.
And if neither of them had been there, it would have been somebody else a few months later.
There are times when the, you know, just the, a lot, often it's the combination of the right ideas are in place and the right experimental data is in place to point in the right direction and it's just waiting for somebody who's going to find it.
Maybe to go back to your aliens, I guess the one thing I often wonder about aliens is would they have the same fundamental physics ideas as we have in mathematics?
Would their math, you know, would they...
How much is this really intrinsic to our minds?
If you start out with a different kind of mind, would you end up with a different ideas of what fundamental physics is or what the structure of mathematics is?
So this is why, if I was...
You know, I like video games.
The way I would do it as a curious being, so first experiment I'd like to do is run Earth over many thousands of times and see if our particular...
No, you know what?
I wouldn't do the full evolution.
I would start at Homo sapiens first and then see the evolution of Homo sapiens millions of times and see how the ideas of science would evolve.
Like, would you get How would physics evolve?
How would math evolve? I would particularly just be curious about the notation they come up with.
Every once in a while, I would throw miracles at them to mess with them and stuff.
And then I would also like to run Earth from the very beginning to see if evolution will produce different kinds of brains that would then produce different kinds of mathematics and physics.
And then finally, I would probably millions of times run the universe over to see what kind of...
What kind of environments and what kind of life would be created to then lead to intelligent life, to then lead to theories of mathematics and physics and to see the full range.
And like sort of like Darwin, kind of Mark.
Okay, it took them, what is it?
Several hundred million years to come up with calculus.
I would just like keep noting how long it took and get an average and see which ideas are difficult and which are not and then conclusively sort of figure out if it's more collective intelligence or singular intelligence that's responsible for shifts and for big phase shifts and breakthroughs in science.
If I was playing a video game and got a chance to run this whole thing.
Yeah. We're talking about books.
Before I distract you, it's horrible. Yeah, so that's one thing I recommend is the books from the original people, especially Heisenberg, about how that happened.
There's also a very, very good kind of history of Of the kind of what happened during this 20th century in physics and, you know, up to the time of the Standard Model in 1973.
It's called The Second Creation by Bob Kreese and Mann.
That's one of the best ones.
I know that's... But the one thing that I can say is that...
So that book, I think, forget when it was, late 80s, 90s...
The problem is that there just hasn't been much that's actually worked out since then.
So most of the books that are kind of trying to tell you about all the glorious things that have happened since 1973, they're mostly telling you about how glorious things are, which actually don't really work.
The argument people sometimes make in favor of these books is, well, oh, they're really great because you want to do something that will get kids excited, and so they're getting excited about doing something that's not really quite working.
It doesn't really matter. The main thing is get them excited.
The other argument is, you know, wait a minute.
If you're getting people excited about ideas that are wrong, you're actually kind of discrediting the whole scientific enterprise in a not really good way.
So there's these problems.
So my general feeling about expository stuff is, yeah, to the extent you can do it kind of honestly and well, that's great.
There are a lot of people doing that now.
But to the extent that you're just trying to get people excited Excited and enthusiastic by kind of telling them stuff which isn't really true.
You really shouldn't be doing that.
You obviously have a much better intuition about physics.
I tend to, in the space of AI, for example, you could You could use certain kinds of language, like calling things intelligent that could rub people the wrong way, but I never had a problem with that kind of thing.
You know, saying that a program can learn its way without any human supervision as AlphaZero does to play chess.
To me, that...
It may not be intelligence, but it sure seems like a few steps down the path towards intelligence.
I think that's a very peculiar property of systems that can be engineered.
Even if the idea is fuzzy, even if you're not really sure what intelligence is, Or like if you don't have a deep fundamental understanding or even a model what intelligence is, if you build a system that sure as heck is impressive and showing some of the signs of what previously thought impossible for a non-intelligent system, then that's impressive and that's inspiring and that's okay to celebrate.
In physics, Because you're not engineering anything.
You're just now swimming in the space directly when you do theoretical physics.
It could be more dangerous.
You could be out too far away from shore.
Yeah. Well, the problem...
I think physics is in a...
I think it's actually hard for people even to believe or really understand how...
That this particular kind of physics has gotten itself into a really unusual and strange and historically unusual state, which is not really...
I mean, I spent half my life among mathematicians and half my physicists, and, you know, mathematics is kind of doing fine.
People are making progress, and it has all the usual problems, but also...
So you could have a...
But I just...
I don't know. I've never seen anything at all happening in mathematics like what's happened in this specific area in physics.
It's just... The kind of sociology of the way this field works, banging up against this harder problem without anything from experiment to help it, it's led to some really kind of problematic things.
So it's one thing to kind of oversimplify or to slightly misrepresent, to try to explain things in a way that's not quite right, but it's another thing to start promoting to people As a success, as ideas which really completely failed.
And so, I mean, I'm kind of very, very specific.
If you have people, I won't name any names, for instance, coming on certain podcasts like yours, telling the world, you know, this is a huge success and this is really wonderful, and it's just not true.
And this is really problematic, and it carries a serious danger of, you know, once when people realize that this is what's going on, you know, they...
The loss of credibility of science is a real, real problem for our society, and you don't want people to have an all-too-good reason to think that what they're being What they're being told by some of the best institutions in our country and our authorities is not true.
It's a problem.
That's obviously a characteristic of not just physics, it's sociology.
And it's, I mean, obviously in the space of politics, it's the history of politics.
You sell ideas to people even when you don't have any proof that those ideas actually work in the U.S. because if they've worked, and that seems to be the case throughout history.
And just like you said, it's human beings running up against a really hard problem I'm not sure if this is a particular trajectory through the progress of physics that we're dealing with now, or it's just the natural progress of science.
You run up against a really difficult stage of a field, and Different people behave differently in the face of that.
Some sell books and sort of tell narratives that are beautiful and so on.
They're not necessarily grounded in solutions that have proven themselves.
Others kind of put their head down quietly, keep doing the work.
Others sort of pivot to different fields.
And that's kind of like, yeah, ants scattering.
And then you have fields like machine learning, which there's a few folks mostly scattered away from machine learning In the 90s, in the winter of AI, AI winter, as they call it.
But a few people kept their head down, and now they're called the fathers of deep learning.
And they didn't think of it that way.
And in fact, if there's another AI winter, they'll just probably keep working on it anyway.
Sort of like loyal aunts to a particular thing.
Sure, yeah, yeah. So it's interesting, but you're sort of saying that we should be careful overhyping things that have not proven themselves because people will lose trust in the scientific process.
But unfortunately, there's been other ways in which people have lost trust in the scientific process.
That ultimately has to do actually with all the same kind of behavior as you're highlighting, which is Not being honest and transparent about the flaws of mistakes of the past.
Yeah, I mean, that's always a problem.
But this particular field, it's always a strange one.
I mean, I think in the sense that there's a lot of public fascination with it, that it seems to speak
to kind of our deepest questions about, you know, what is this physical reality? Where do we come
from? And what, and these kind of deep issues. So there's this unusual fascination with it.
Mathematics is, for instance, very different. Nobody's that interested in mathematics. Nobody
really kind of expects to learn really great deep things about the world from mathematics that much.
They don't ask mathematicians that.
So it draws this kind of unusual amount of attention.
And it really is historically in a really unusual state.
It's gotten itself way kind of down a blind alley in a way which...
It's hard to find other historical parallels too.
But sort of to push back a little bit, there's power to inspiring people.
And if I just empirically look, physicists are really good at combining science and philosophy and communicating it.
Like there's something about physics often that forces you to build a strong intuition about the way reality works.
And that allows you to think through and communicate about all kinds of questions.
If you see physicists, it's always fascinating to take on problems that have nothing to do with their particular discipline.
They think in interesting ways and they're able to communicate their thinking in interesting ways.
And so in some sense, they have a responsibility not just to do science, but to inspire.
And not responsibility, but the opportunity, and thereby, I would say, a little bit of a responsibility.
Yeah, yeah, and sometimes, but, I don't know, anyway, it's hard to say, because different, there's many, many people doing this kind of thing with different degrees of success and whatever.
I guess one thing, but, I mean, what's kind of front and center for me is kind of a more parochial interest, is just kind of what What damage do you do to the subject itself?
Ignoring, misrepresenting, you know, what high school students think about string theory and not that doesn't matter much, but what the smartest undergraduates or the smartest graduate students in the world think about it and what paths you're leading them down and what story you're telling them and what textbooks you're making them read and what they're hearing.
And so a lot of what's motivated me is more to try to speak to It's kind of a specific population of people to make sure that, look, you know, people, it doesn't matter so much what the average person on the street thinks about string theory, but, you know, What the best students at Columbia or Harvard or Princeton or whatever who really want to change work in this field and want to work that way, what they know about it, what they think about it, and that they not be going to the field being misled and believing that a certain story,
this is where this is all going, this is what I got to do, that's important to me.
Well, in general, for graduate students, for people who seek to be experts in the field, diversity of ideas is really powerful, and is getting into this local pocket of ideas that people hold on to for several decades is not good, no matter what the idea.
I would say no matter if the idea is right or wrong, because there's no such thing as right in the long term.
Like, it's right for now.
Until somebody builds on something much bigger on top of it.
It might end up being right, but being a tiny subset of a much bigger thing.
So you always should question sort of the ways of the past.
Yeah. So how to kind of achieve that kind of...
Diversity of thought and within kind of the sociology of how we organize scientific research.
I know this is one thing that I think it's very interesting that Sabina Hassenfelder has very interesting things to say about it.
And I think also Lee Smolin and his book, which is also about that, very much in agreement with them that there's, anyway, there's a really kind of important Questions about how research in this field is organized and what can you do to get more diversity of thought and get people thinking about a wider range of ideas.
At the bottom, I think humility always helps.
The problem is that it's also a combination of humility to know when you're wrong, but also you have to have a certain very serious lack of humility to believe that you're gonna make progress on some of these problems.
I think you have to have both modes to switch between them when needed.
Let me ask you a question you're probably not gonna wanna answer, because you're focused on the mathematics of things, and mathematics can't answer the why questions, but let me ask you anyway.
Do you think there's meaning to this whole thing?
What do you think is the meaning of life?
Why are we here? I don't know, yeah, I was thinking about this, so the, it did occur to me, one interesting thing about that question is that you don't, so I have, This life in mathematics and this life in physics, and I see some of my physicist colleagues kind of People are often asking them, what's the meaning of life?
And they're writing books about the meaning of life and teaching courses about the meaning of life.
But then I realized that no one ever asked my mathematician colleagues.
Nobody ever asked mathematicians.
Everybody just kind of assumes, okay, well, you people are studying about that.
Whatever you're doing, it's maybe very interesting, but it's clearly not going to tell me anything useful about the meaning of my life.
And I'm afraid a lot of my point of view is that If people realized how little difference there was between what the mathematicians are doing and what a lot of these theoretical physicists are doing, they might understand that it's a bit misguided to look for deep insight into the meaning of life from many theoretical physicists.
They're people, and they may have interesting things to say about this.
You're right, they know a lot about physical reality and about About, in some sense, about metaphysics, about what is real of this kind.
But you're also, to my mind, I think you're also making a bit of a mistake that you're looking to...
I mean, I'm very, very aware that, you know, I've led a very pleasant and fairly privileged existence without many challenges of different kinds and of a certain kind.
And I'm really not in no way the kind of person that a lot of people who are looking to try to understand in some sense the meaning of life in the sense of the challenges that they're facing in life.
I'm really the wrong person for you to be asking about this.
If struggle is somehow a thing that's core to meaning, perhaps mathematicians are just quietly the ones who are most equipped to answer that question, if in fact the creation or at least experiencing beauty Is at the core of the meaning of life, because it seems like mathematics is the methodology by which you can most purely explore beautiful things, right?
So in some sense, maybe we should talk to mathematicians more.
Yeah, yeah, maybe.
But unfortunately, I think people do have a somewhat correct perception that what these people are doing every day or whatever is pretty far removed from anything.
Yeah, from what's kind of close to what I do every day and what my typical concerns are.
So you may learn something very interesting by talking to mathematicians, but you're probably not going to get what you were hoping.
So when you put the pen and paper down, and you're not thinking about physics, and you're not thinking about mathematics, and you just get to breathe in the air and look around you and realize that you're going to die one day.
Yeah. Do you think about that?
Your ideas will live on, but you, the human?
Not especially much.
Certainly, I've been getting older.
I'm now 64 years old.
You start to realize, well, there's probably less ahead than there was behind, and so that starts to become, you know, what do I think about that?
Maybe I should actually get serious about getting some things done, which I may otherwise not have time to do, which I... This didn't seem to be a problem when I was younger, but that's the main way in which that thought occurred.
But the Stoics are big on this.
Meditating on mortality helps you more intensely appreciate the beauty when you do experience it.
I suppose that's true, but yeah, it's not something I spend a lot of time trying, but yeah.
Day to day, you just enjoy the puzzles, the mathematics.
Just enjoy, yeah, our life in general.
Life is, have a perfectly pleasant life and enjoy it.
I often think, wow, I'm really enjoying this.
Things are going well. Yeah, life is pretty amazing.
I think you and I are pretty lucky we get to live on this nice little earth with a nice little comfortable climate and we get to have this nice little podcast conversation.
Thank you so much for spending your valuable time with me today and having this conversation.
Thank you. Thank you.
Thanks for listening to this conversation with Peter White.
To support this podcast, please check out our sponsors in the description.
And now, let me leave you some words from Richard Feynman.
The first principle is that you must not fool yourself, and you are the easiest person to fool.
Export Selection